Gödel’s Incompleteness Theorems
نویسنده
چکیده
In 1931, when he was only 25 years of age, the great Austrian logician Kurt Gödel (1906– 1978) published an epoch-making paper [16] (for an English translation see [8, pp. 5–38]), in which he proved that an effectively definable consistent mathematical theory which is strong enough to prove Peano’s postulates of elementary arithmetic cannot prove its own consistency. In fact, Gödel first established that there always exist sentences φ in the language of Peano Arithmetic which are true, but are undecidable; that is, neither φ nor ¬φ is provable from Peano’s postulates. This is known as Gödel’s First Incompleteness Theorem. This theorem is quite remarkable in its own right because it shows that Peano’s well-known postulates, which by and large are considered as an axiomatic basis for elementary arithmetic, cannot prove all true statements about natural numbers. But Gödel went even further. He showed that his first incompleteness theorem implies that an effectively definable sufficiently strong consistent mathematical theory cannot prove its own consistency. This theorem became known as Gödel’s Second Incompleteness Theorem. Since then the two theorems are referred to as Gödel’s Incompleteness Theorems. They became landmark theorems and had a huge impact on the subsequent development of logic. In order to give more context, we step further back in time. The idea of formalizing logic goes back to the ancient Greek philosophers. One of the first to pursue it was the great German philosopher and mathematician Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz (1646–1716). His dream was to develop a universal symbolic language, which would reduce all debate to simple calculation. The next major figure in this pursuit was the English mathematician George Boole (1815–1864), who has provided the first successful steps in this direction. This line of research was developed to a great extent by the famous German mathematician and philosopher Gottlob Frege (1848–1925), and reached its peak in the works of Bertrand Russell (1872–1970) and Alfred North Whitehead (1861–1947). Their magnum opus Principia Mathematica [27] has provided relatively simple, yet rigorous formal basis for logic, and became very influential in the development of the twentieth century logic. ∗Mathematical Sciences; Dept. 3MB, Box 30001; New Mexico State University; Las Cruces, NM 88003; [email protected]. We recall that a theory is consistent if it does not prove contradiction. More details on the work of Boole, Frege, and Russell and Whitehead can be found on our webpage http://www.cs.nmsu.edu/historical-projects/; see the historical projects [24, 7]. The work of Boole has resulted in an important concept of Boolean algebra, which is discussed in great length in a series of historical projects [3, 2, 1], also available on our webpage.
منابع مشابه
Gödel’s Completeness and Incompleteness Theorems
This paper will discuss the completeness and incompleteness theorems of Kurt Gödel. These theorems have a profound impact on the philosophical perception of mathematics and call into question the readily apparent strength of the system itself. This paper will discuss the theorems themselves, their philosophical impact on the study of mathematics and some of the logical background necessary to u...
متن کاملCitations about Gödel’s Theorems
This is a short account of various notes and opinions about Gödel’s theorems I found in my books. It should ease the task of actually writing something about Gödel’s First Incompleteness Theorem. Citations about Gödel’s Theorems
متن کاملTeaching Gödel’s incompleteness theorems
The basic notions of logic—predicate logic, Peano arithmetic, incompleteness theorems, etc.—have for long been an advanced topic. In the last decades, they became more widely taught, in philosophy, mathematics, and computer science departments, to graduate and to undergraduate students. Many textbooks now present these notions, in particular the incompleteness theorems. Having taught these noti...
متن کاملWhat Gödel’s Theorem Really Proves
It is proved in this paper the undecidable formula involved in Gödel’s first incompleteness theorem would be inconsistent if the formal system where it is defined were complete. So, before proving the formula is undecidable it is necessary to assume the system is not complete in order to ensure the formula is not inconsistent. Consequently, Gödel proof does not prove the formal system is incomp...
متن کاملOn the information-theoretic approach to Gödel’s incompleteness theorem
In this paper we briefly review and analyze three published proofs of Chaitin’s theorem, the celebrated information-theoretic version of Gödel’s incompleteness theorem. Then, we discuss our main perplexity concerning a key step common to all these demonstrations.
متن کاملGödel’s Incompleteness Theorems Hand-in Exercises and Model Solutions
b) (3 points) Define a new function F ′ by: F ′(0,m, ~y, x) = G(~y,Km(x)) F ′(n+ 1,m, ~y, x) = H(n, F ′(n,m, ~y, x), ~y,Km−̇(n+1)(x)) Recall that Km−̇(n+1) means: the function K applied m−̇(n+1) times. Prove: if n ≤ m then ∀k[F ′(n,m+ k, ~y, x) = F ′(n,m, ~y,Kk(x))] c) (3 points) Prove by induction: F (z, ~y, x) = F ′(z, z, ~y, x) and conclude that F is primitive recursive, also without the assump...
متن کامل